Skip to main content

Do Dretske and Huemer Agree on Perception?

Fred Dretske has formulated a representational (or indirect realist) account of perception that includes the following two features:

Fred Dretske
(1) Representational Vehicles/Contents

Dretske first distinguishes between representational vehicle and representational contents as follows: "There are representational vehicles—the objects, events, or conditions that represent—and representational contents—the conditions or situations the vehicle represents as being so" (Dretske 68).

(2) Qualia

Secondly, Dretske appeals to qualia: "qualia are properties that physical objects, the ones we experience, normally have. They are not properties that experiences have" (Dretske 69).

Michael Huemer
In contrast to Dretske, Michael Huemer formulates and defends a version of direct realism in his book Skepticism and the Veil of Perception. Huemer gives the following rough characterization of direct realism: “Direct realism holds that in perception, we are directly aware of external phenomena” (Huemer x). In order to achieve a deeper understanding of Huemer's direct realism, we need to understand his conception of awareness. For Huemer, "awareness is always awareness of something. Logically, awareness is a relation between a being who is aware (the ‘subject of awareness’) and that of which he is aware (the ‘object of awareness’)" (Huemer 51).

More precisely, Huemer defines awareness as follows (Huemer 55):

S is aware of x if and only if:


i. S has an assertive mental representation (an apprehension),

ii. x exists and at least roughly satisfies the content of that representation, and

iii. it is not accidental (not due to chance) that the content of the representation is satisfied.

According to Huemer, awareness comes in two forms: indirect and direct. He explains this distinction as follows:

In general, you are indirectly aware of x if you are aware of x, but your awareness of x is based on your awareness of something else. You are directly aware of x if you are aware of x, and your awareness of x is not based on your awareness of anything else. (Huemer 55)

So representationalists like Dretske ostensibly "believe that those mental states [that exist purely in our minds and that ‘represent’ external objects] are the only things that we can be directly aware of. It is [this] thesis that defines indirect realism" (Huemer 79). In contrast, "A ‘version of direct realism’ would be any theory of perception which implies that in perception, we are directly aware of something external to the mind" (Huemer 79).

Direct and indirect realism are thus mutually exclusive. We might conclude, then, that Dretske and Huemer are fundamentally at odds. Intriguingly, however, Huemer, like Dretske, also distinguishes between vehicles and contents: "The fundamental mistake that seems to make indirect realism plausible . . . is a confusion between an object of awareness and a vehicle of awareness. An object of awareness is that of which one is aware. A vehicle of awareness is that by which one is aware of it" (Huemer 81).

Given that both Dretske and Huemer make a vehicle/content distinction, might there be common ground in Dretske's and Huemer's accounts? Our answer will depend on which sorts of things are supposed to count as representational vehicles on Dretske's account. Dretske himself isn't particularly clear on this issue, though he leaves room for the possibility that brain states are a kind of representational vehicle. Huemer would likely agree on that count. We might wonder, though, what would prevent a representational perceptual experience itself from being a vehicle of awareness in Huemer's sense. If Dretske insists that it is the representational perceptual experience itself that one is aware of, then Dretske's account ultimately diverges from Huemer's. On the other hand, if Dretske's account is flexible enough to allow that a representational perceptual experience as a whole might be that by which one is aware of things in the world, then Dretske and Huemer might ultimately agree on perception.

References

Dretske, F. 2003: Experience As Representation. Philosophical Issues, Vol. 13, 67-82.

Huemer, M. 2001: Skepticism and the Veil of Perception. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Negative Afterimage

Reber Shukri Professor Vaughn Negative afterimage is a stimulus which elicits a positive image. In order to experience this, one can look at a bright source of light and then look away to a dark area. The way negative afterimage works is when the eye's photo-receptors which are the rods and cones adapt to over stimulation and lose sensitivity. The photo-receptors which are constantly exposed to the same stimulus will fatigue their supply of photo pigment, resulting a decrease in signal to the brain. The way negative afterimage connects to perception is because of bottom up processing where the stimulus influences what we perceive. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=szy8iNCljlQ <Link to the video

Illusions that Confuse Multiple Senses

In this video, several illusions are shown that deceive your senses. Illusions such as the Zöllner Illusion and the Poggendorff illusion confuse our bottom up processing by tricking our vision. However, our vision isn't the only sense that these illusions can confuse, blind individuals presented with raised versions of the same illusions are also confused by them. These illusions effect the visual and touch systems by confusing our bottom up processing by tricking out sight and touch. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Je1mkzRU5rc&t=64s
          Evolution of Camouflage & First World War Dazzle Paint Jobs           The origins of modern camouflage owes itself to 19th century naturalist painters.  The most notable of these in the development of knowledge of camouflage was Abbot H, Thayer.  While he harbored some strange views of the scientific development of animal camouflage (all animals were "camouflaged")  He noticed the effect of disruptive patterning and countershading.  He noted that animal markings tended to obstruct their shape in nature.  Their coloring added with this made them often completely invisible. By going from darker shades on top to lighter on the bottom animals canceled out the way we see objects by light illuminated them top down.  Black also aided in disruptive schemes. An example of Countershading. Abbot's demonstration of disruptive patterns. In this image we can see how disruptive patterns observe...